58
J. Rosaler / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 50 (2015) 54–69
relationship that it takes to underwrite reduction. The expression
lim
T ¼ T is not mathematically well-defined, as there is no
mind literature, were prompted to advocate for a more local
approach to reduction in which a lower-level description accounts
for the successes of a higher-level description through many
context-specific derivations employing context-specific bridge
principles, rather than through a single global derivation employ-
ing the same set of bridge principles for all systems in the high-
level description's domain. In particular, Kim has argued that
while multiple realization rules out “structure-independent”
reductions of psychology to physical science, it does allow for
“structure-specific” local reductions between these levels (Kim,
1992). Following Kim, Dizadji-Bahmani et al. also have advocated a
local response to anti-reductionist arguments from multiple rea-
lizability in the context of their wider defence of Nagelian reduc-
tion (Dizadji-Bahmani et al., 2010). Similar views can be found in
the work of Churchland (1986, chap. 7), Enc (1983), Hooker (1981),
Lewis (1969), Bickle (2013), and Schaffner (2012). The main goal of
the present analysis is to show explicitly how this sort of local
approach, which has been developed primarily in discussions
about reduction in philosophy of mind and general philosophy of
science, can be imported into methodological discussions of inter-
theoretic reduction specifically within physics.
fϵi-0g
l
h
precise or general definition of what it is for one theory to be a
limit or limiting case of another. Moreover, it is unclear from this
expression whether the prescription to take the limit is to be
understood literally or in some loosened sense. For example, if we
are to understand the claim that Newtonian mechanics is the limit
as vc-0 of special relativity literally, then the claim is patently false,
since the limit of special relativity as vc-0 is a theory in which
nothing moves, not Newtonian mechanics (assuming we take c,
the speed of light, to be constant, as it is for all real physical
systems). For this paradigmatic case to be regarded as an instance
of limit-based reduction, it seems necessary to adopt a more
liberal construal of the term “limit”—for example, by making use
v
c
of first- or higher-order approximations in Taylor expansions in
(where only the zero-th order term of such an expansion gives the
actual limit of this series as vc-0). On the other hand, in other
cases, including certain discussions of the thermodynamic limit of
statistical mechanics, in which the number of degrees of freedom
in a system is taken to infinity, the limiting process is interpreted
literally—for example, when it is pointed out that the only way to
recover the discontinuities of certain functions in thermodynamics
from statistical mechanics is to literally take the limit as the
number of degrees of freedom approaches infinity. Beyond the
points of vagueness already mentioned, it is not clear on this
approach which parts of Th and Tl must be related by these “limits”
3.1. The need for local reduction in physics: an illustrative example
An example, concerning the relationship between classical and
quantum mechanics, will serve to make my general point that global
reductions are not available in all cases where the conventional
wisdom requires reduction to occur, and that only a weaker (but still
highly non-trivial), more local form of reduction is available in such
cases. As we will see, the source of trouble for global approaches to
reduction in physics is that it is often not just the broad generalities
that characterize the theories—which are common to all models of a
given theory—but also specific details that differentiate models of the
same theory, that play a role in the low-level theory's account of why
the high-level theory works in a given case. In other words, system-
or context-specific details often play a necessary role in accounting
for the high-level theory's success on the basis of the low-level
theory in a given case, and this precludes the sort of generality
demanded by global forms of reduction.
The conventional wisdom about the progress of physics asserts
that quantum mechanics has strictly superseded quantum
mechanics in the sense that any system whose behavior can be
accurately modelled in classical mechanics also can be modelled,
and modelled more accurately, in quantum mechanics.5 Here,
I will argue that any demonstration to this effect could not
possibly, even in principle, take the form of a global reduction.
Consider two systems in the domain of classical mechanics, both
of which are described by the same classical model of a simple
harmonic oscillator: the first system is a mass on a spring; the
second is an electric charge of the same mass moving along a path
bored through the axis of a uniform spherical charge distribution
(one can show that in the second case, there will be a restoring
force on the charge that varies linearly with its distance from the
center of the sphere). Assume moreover that frictional/radiation
effects can be ignored in both systems, and that the linear
restoring force in both cases is characterized by the same effective
spring constant. Assuming that macroscopic bodies do belong to
in order for the relation lim T ¼ T to hold; presumably, not
fϵi-0g
l
h
just any limiting relation between any two parts of the theories
will do. Finally, limit-based approaches tend to differ on what
constraints, if any, should be placed on the parameters
ϵi—for
example, whether they are supposed to be dimensionless, or may
also be dimensionful constants of nature.
Given that this approach offers very little by way of precise
characterizations or clear commitments as to the nature of
reductive relations in physics, it seems possible to take many
cases that we might wish to characterize as successful reductions
and categorize them as instances of limit-based reduction. But if
existing formulations of the limit-based approach succeed at
accommodating many cases in physics, it is largely for the reason
that they tell us so little, and are so vague, about the general
requirements for reduction. It seems possible to count any reduc-
tion as an instance of limit-based reduction as long as the
reduction somehow incorporates a procedure that may liberally
be construed as “taking a limit.” The worry, then, is that this
approach, at least in its existing formulations, may give the false
impression of providing an authoritative, general account of
reduction in physics in spite of having offered little by way of
general insight beyond the assertion that, in cases of reduction,
something like a limit is somehow involved in the explanation of
the high-level theory's success on the basis of the low-level theory.
Recalling the focus here on comparing global and local forms of
reduction, I should point out that since the limit-based approach is
conventionally formulated in terms of limiting relations between
whole theories, it seems most natural to read this approach as a
global strategy for reduction. However, given the vagueness of
existing formulations of this approach, it does not appear that
anything precludes interpreting this relation on a more local basis.
Nevertheless, such a formulation is still vulnerable to worries
about precisely the sort of vagueness that allows for this vast
flexibility of interpretation.
5
There is a sense in which this particular case might appear to be less than an
ideal example, given the various added complexities brought about by the
notorious interpretational difficulties that afflict quantum mechanics, which seem
as though they should bear quite heavily on the relation between quantum and
classical descriptions of real physical systems. However, these difficulties do not
affect my central point here, as long as we are safe in assuming that the correct
interpretation of quantum mechanics, whatever that happens to be, is able to
underwrite the success of classical descriptions on a case-by-case basis.
3. Local reduction in physics
It was largely in response to critiques of global Nagel/Schaffner
reduction that a number of authors, mostly in the philosophy of